Databac

Austin, John

Publié le 16/05/2020

Extrait du document

Ci-dessous un extrait traitant le sujet : Austin, John Ce document contient 1067 mots soit 2 pages. Pour le télécharger en entier, envoyez-nous un de vos documents grâce à notre système gratuit d’échange de ressources numériques. Cette aide totalement rédigée en format pdf sera utile aux lycéens ou étudiants ayant un devoir à réaliser ou une leçon à approfondir en Philosophie.

« Austin, John (1790-1859) Although written in the early nineteenth century, Austin's is probably the most coherent and sustained account ofthe theory of legal positivism.

The complex relationships between legal positivism and the concepts of morality andpolitics are explored by him but are often neglected or misunderstood in modern commentaries.

John Austin became in 1829 the first Professor of Jurisprudence at the newly established University of London, having previouslyspent a brief spell in the army, followed by a somewhat longer period of work in barristers' chambers as an equitydraftsman.

In preparation to take up his chair, he spent two years studying in Bonn, acquainting himself withclassical Romano-German legal science.

A neighbour of James Mill and Jeremy Bentham , he was much of their intellectual circle, and had John Stuart Mill as a student.

His main work was a systematic explanation of some basic social concepts in terms which have been received as the classical statement of 'legal positivism', according towhich law is dependent on the will of superior(s) over inferior(s) (see Legal positivism §2 ).

Austin wanted all lawyers to commence their studies with the cognitive sciences, logic and ethics.

Politics and the study of law were seen byhim as subcategories of ethics.

More than half of his introductory series of lectures was given over to an expositionof the principle of utility - seen either as the index to the laws of God, or as the rational basis of ethics.

He saidthat all laws (apart from scientific laws) were set to intelligent beings by intelligent beings, having power over them.There are two basic types of laws - those set by God for people and those set by people for others.

Of the lawsset by God, Austin said that he would normally call these 'natural' laws, but as this word is likely to be confusedwith aspects of sociology, he would instead call them 'divine' laws.

He recognized that 'non-believers' would preferthe word 'ethics'.

On either view, these provide the standard by which all other laws should be judged.

Manymodern positivist scholars think that positivism and natural law are opposed to each other - not so for Austin.Austin said that of laws set by people there can also be two types - those set by them as political superiors(positive law) and those set by them in other capacities (positive morality).

Having set out the basic categories ofethics, positive law and positive morality, Austin went on to explain their common and distinctive features.

Theyhave in common the concepts of 'commands', 'duties' and 'sanctions'.

The intelligent being or person lays downsome general rule for the guidance of human conduct.

If it is not complied with, the maker of the rule can exact some detriment for non-compliance.

The distinctive features of 'positive law' (the law of the state) are that it comprises rules made by 'sovereigns' addressed to 'subjects' within an 'independent political society'.

While theseideas are scorned by most contemporary legal theorists, they remain fundamental in international politics and foreignaffairs policy.

Austin made it clear that the study of politics is logically and socially prior to the study of state law.Without political stability there is no state, and without the state no law of the state.

The most contentiousaspects of Austin's views were his claims that 'sovereigns' cannot be bound by state laws, and that the 'laws' operating between states would be better viewed as 'international positive morality'.

Both points relate to the roleof coercion, assuming that the author of a coercive law cannot, logically, also be subject to it, and that stateboundaries limit the enforceability of state laws, but not necessarily their range of application.

Some suggest thathis separation of the concepts of positive (state) law, positive (existing or customary) morality, and ethics (thecritical base), entails that the positive law can be understood or implemented without understanding its relationshipto the other factors.

This is plainly wrong.

There has been much debate about this 'separation of law and morality'.Most writers on the topic forget that Austin said - 'Positive law (or jus), positive morality (or mos ) together with the principles which form the test of both, are the inseparably connected parts of a vast organic whole' ( 1861-3: 17).

An unfulfilled project of his was to write a book on The Principles and Relations of Jurisprudence and Ethics .

It follows from Austin's analysis that as we are dealing with three types of rules there are also three types of dutiesas well as three types of commands and sanctions.

Austin said that if there should be any conflict between theduties of positive law and the duties of ethics or divine law, then because the sanctions which God could imposewould greatly outweigh those which could be imposed by the human makers of positive law, it would accord withthe principles of utility to act in accordance with the natural or divine law and not the law of the state.

The law ofthe state, he said, had its basis in the positive morality of the wider community, and should be guided in itsdevelopment by the positive morality of the legal and international communities.

Austin had no time for 'the childishfiction employed by our judges, that judiciary law or common law is not made by them, but is a miraculoussomething made by nobody, existing, I suppose from eternity, and merely declared from time to time by the judges'(1861-3: 634 ).

He explains at some length how it is that judges make the law rather than just find it, and entitles chapters 35-9 of his Lectures 'Judicial Legislation' .

In its conceptual aspects, Austin's approach influenced the work of people such as W.N.

Hohfeld, and in its social aspects has much in common with the writing of the later legalrealists.

Austin's strongest supporter was his wife Sarah, who was accomplished and well known in the intellectualcircles of London and Paris, and with a number of important translations to her credit.

As a teacher, Austin was notconspicuously successful, and his periods of formal academic employment were quite brief, at the University ofLondon (1829-33) and at the Inns of Court in London (1834).

He also worked with the British Criminal LawCommission (1833) and for a short period as a Commissioner to the Royal Commission on Malta (1836-8).. »

↓↓↓ APERÇU DU DOCUMENT ↓↓↓

Liens utiles